Enter a player name to begin or load your saved progress.
The Latin translation for the legal maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is *lex iniusta non est lex*.
Answer: True
Explanation: The Latin translation for the legal maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is indeed *lex iniusta non est lex*. This phrase is central to discussions in natural law philosophy.
The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" primarily serves to challenge the binding authority of morally deficient laws.
Answer: True
Explanation: The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" fundamentally challenges the binding authority of laws that are deemed morally deficient, asserting that such laws lack true legal force.
The Latin phrase *lex iniusta non est lex* signifies that laws lacking justice are considered invalid.
Answer: True
Explanation: The Latin phrase *lex iniusta non est lex* signifies the principle that a law which is unjust cannot be considered a true law. It is a cornerstone concept in natural law philosophy, asserting that morality is intrinsically linked to the validity of law.
The principle "An unjust law is no law at all" suggests that justice is merely a desirable quality for law, not a requirement.
Answer: False
Explanation: The principle "An unjust law is no law at all" posits that justice is not merely a desirable quality but a fundamental requirement for a rule to be considered a true law.
The idea that unjust laws might lack validity has remained static throughout history.
Answer: False
Explanation: The idea that unjust laws might lack validity has evolved significantly throughout history, appearing in various forms from ancient religious texts to medieval philosophy and modern political discourse.
The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" has gained recognition as a standard legal maxim globally.
Answer: True
Explanation: The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" has achieved recognition as a standard legal maxim globally, indicating its widespread influence and acceptance in legal and philosophical discourse.
What is the Latin translation for the legal maxim "An unjust law is no law at all"?
Answer: *lex iniusta non est lex*
Explanation: The Latin translation for the legal maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is *lex iniusta non est lex*. This phrase is central to discussions in natural law philosophy.
Globally, the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is recognized as:
Answer: A standard legal maxim
Explanation: The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" has achieved recognition as a standard legal maxim globally, indicating its widespread influence and acceptance in legal and philosophical discourse.
What does Augustine of Hippo's statement, *nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit*, imply about the nature of law?
Answer: Justice is a necessary condition for a true law.
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo's statement, *nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit*, implies that justice is not merely an attribute but a fundamental prerequisite for a rule to be considered a true law. It posits a necessary connection between legality and morality.
What did Augustine of Hippo consider the essential quality of a true law?
Answer: Justice
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo posited that justice is the indispensable quality of a true law. He famously asserted that a rule lacking justice cannot be considered a law in the authentic sense.
What is the primary purpose of the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" as stated in the text?
Answer: To support the concept of natural law.
Explanation: The primary purpose of the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is to underscore the tenets of natural law theory, which posits that the legitimacy of legal authority is intrinsically tied to its alignment with fundamental principles of goodness and righteousness.
How has the idea that unjust laws might lack validity evolved historically, according to the text?
Answer: It evolved from biblical references through medieval philosophy to modern thought.
Explanation: The concept that unjust laws may lack validity has evolved historically, tracing its lineage from ancient biblical texts (e.g., Isaiah) through medieval philosophical discourse (Augustine, Aquinas) to modern political thought and activism (Thoreau, King Jr.), demonstrating a persistent philosophical challenge to absolute legal authority when it conflicts with justice.
What is the fundamental connection between justice and law according to the principle "An unjust law is no law at all"?
Answer: Justice is a necessary condition for a true law.
Explanation: The principle "An unjust law is no law at all" establishes a fundamental connection between justice and law, asserting that justice is not merely an attribute but a fundamental prerequisite for a rule to be considered a true law.
The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" primarily supports legal positivism.
Answer: False
Explanation: The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" primarily supports Natural Law theory, which posits that law's validity is intrinsically linked to its moral content and alignment with justice. Legal positivism, in contrast, typically separates law from morality.
Natural law theory posits that human-made laws are valid only if they contradict inherent moral principles.
Answer: False
Explanation: Natural law theory posits that human-made laws are valid only if they *align with* inherent moral principles, not contradict them. Laws that fundamentally violate natural moral law are often considered invalid or non-binding within this framework.
The legitimacy of a law, according to the maxim, stems solely from the authority that enacts it.
Answer: False
Explanation: According to the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all," legitimacy stems not solely from the enacting authority but critically from the law's justice and moral content. An unjust law, even if enacted by a legitimate authority, is considered to lack true legal standing.
Natural law theory posits that human-made laws are valid only if they contradict inherent moral principles.
Answer: False
Explanation: Natural law theory posits that human-made laws are valid only if they *align with* inherent moral principles, not contradict them. Laws that fundamentally violate natural moral law are often considered invalid or non-binding within this framework.
The legitimacy of a law, according to the maxim, stems solely from the authority that enacts it.
Answer: False
Explanation: According to the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all," legitimacy stems not solely from the enacting authority but critically from the law's justice and moral content. An unjust law, even if enacted by a legitimate authority, is considered to lack true legal standing.
The maxim implies that the authority enacting a law is irrelevant if the law is unjust.
Answer: True
Explanation: The maxim implies that if a law is profoundly unjust, the authority that enacted it becomes secondary or irrelevant to its legal validity. The moral deficiency of the law itself undermines its claim to authority.
The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is primarily an expression in support of which legal philosophy?
Answer: Natural Law
Explanation: The maxim "An unjust law is no law at all" is fundamentally aligned with Natural Law theory, which posits that laws derive their legitimacy from inherent moral principles or a higher natural order. It asserts that legal authority is contingent upon the law's adherence to justice and goodness.
The core idea behind natural law theory, as related to the maxim, is that:
Answer: Human-made laws are only valid if they align with inherent moral principles.
Explanation: Natural law theory posits that there are inherent moral principles or rights that govern human conduct, and that human-made laws are only valid if they align with these natural principles. The maxim suggests that laws contradicting these fundamental moral truths lack true legal authority.
How does the concept of legitimacy relate to the maxim "An unjust law is no law at all"?
Answer: It challenges legitimacy based on moral content and justice.
Explanation: The maxim directly challenges the legitimacy of laws that are unjust. It implies that true legitimacy stems not just from the authority that enacts a law, but also from the law's moral content and its alignment with justice and the common good.
H.L.A. Hart and Lon Fuller are the two natural law theorists most strongly associated with the principle that an unjust law is not a law.
Answer: False
Explanation: This statement is false. While Lon Fuller is a prominent natural law theorist associated with this principle, H.L.A. Hart is generally considered a legal positivist. John Finnis is another natural law theorist strongly associated with this principle.
Philosophical and religious writers have historically ignored the concept of objecting to unjust laws.
Answer: False
Explanation: Contrary to this statement, philosophical and religious writers throughout history have extensively engaged with the concept of objecting to unjust laws, often grounding their arguments in principles of higher morality or natural justice.
The biblical passage Isaiah 10 is cited as an early example of objecting to unjust laws.
Answer: True
Explanation: The biblical passage in Isaiah 10, which condemns those who enact oppressive decrees, is cited as an early historical example reflecting the principle of objecting to unjust laws.
Augustine of Hippo believed that a law which is just is not truly a law.
Answer: False
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo's position was that an *unjust* law is not a true law (*lex iniusta non est lex*), not that a *just* law is not a law. His view emphasizes justice as a necessary condition for legal validity.
Augustine of Hippo discussed the idea that an unjust law is not a law while examining the problem of evil.
Answer: True
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo addressed the concept that an unjust law is not a law within his broader theological discourse on the problem of evil. He linked the existence of unjust laws to human deviations from divine goodness and justice.
Thomas Aquinas's major work, *Summa Theologica*, extensively examines the legitimacy of man-made laws.
Answer: True
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas's seminal work, the *Summa Theologica*, provides a comprehensive examination of jurisprudence, including detailed discussions on the nature, purpose, and legitimacy of man-made laws.
According to Thomas Aquinas, the primary criterion for a law's legitimacy is its author.
Answer: False
Explanation: According to Thomas Aquinas, the primary criterion for a law's legitimacy is its purpose: it must be enacted for the common good. While the authority of the author is a necessary condition, it is not the primary criterion.
Thomas Aquinas stipulated that a legitimate law must be enacted by an authority acting within the proper scope of their power.
Answer: True
Explanation: One of Thomas Aquinas's key criteria for a legitimate law is that it must be enacted by a proper authority acting within the legitimate scope of their power, ensuring that the law originates from a rightful source.
Thomas Aquinas believed that legitimate laws should only apply to a select group of individuals.
Answer: False
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas believed that legitimate laws should apply equitably to all individuals, not just a select group. The principle of fairness and the common good necessitated broad application.
Thomas Aquinas cautioned that disobedience to a law should not itself cause harm or lead individuals into committing evil acts.
Answer: True
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas advised that while unjust laws may not be binding, disobedience should be undertaken with prudence, ensuring that the act of defiance does not itself result in greater harm or promote further evil.
Augustine of Hippo's statement *nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit* translates to "for I think a law that is not just, is not actually a law."
Answer: True
Explanation: The Latin statement *nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit*, attributed to Augustine of Hippo, accurately translates to "for I think a law that is not just, is not actually a law," encapsulating his view on the essential nature of justice in law.
Thomas Aquinas used the term "common good" to refer to the benefit of a single powerful individual.
Answer: False
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas defined the "common good" as the collective welfare and flourishing of the entire community or society, not the benefit of a single individual or a select group.
Augustine of Hippo considered justice to be an optional characteristic for a true law.
Answer: False
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo considered justice to be an essential, not optional, characteristic of a true law. He famously stated that a law lacking justice could not be considered a law at all.
Aquinas advised that individuals should always disobey laws that fail his criteria for legitimacy.
Answer: False
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas did not advocate for automatic disobedience to laws failing his criteria. He cautioned that disobedience should not itself cause greater harm or lead to evil acts, implying a need for prudence.
Aquinas's criteria for legitimate laws were intended only for religious laws.
Answer: False
Explanation: While rooted in theological considerations, Thomas Aquinas's criteria for legitimate laws—purpose for the common good, enactment by proper authority, and equitable form—are generally understood to apply to secular, man-made laws as well.
Augustine's view on unjust laws was disconnected from his theological concerns about evil.
Answer: False
Explanation: Augustine's view on unjust laws was intrinsically connected to his theological concerns about evil, as he saw injustice in laws as a manifestation of human departures from divine goodness.
Which two natural law theorists are strongly associated with the principle that an unjust law is not a law?
Answer: John Finnis and Lon Fuller
Explanation: John Finnis and Lon Fuller are two prominent natural law theorists strongly associated with the principle that an unjust law is not a true law, emphasizing the intrinsic connection between law and morality.
Which biblical passage is cited in the text as an early example of objecting to unjust laws?
Answer: Isaiah 10
Explanation: The biblical passage in Isaiah 10, which condemns those who enact oppressive decrees, is cited as an early historical example reflecting the principle of objecting to unjust laws.
What was Augustine of Hippo's famous statement regarding the justice of laws?
Answer: *Nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit*
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo articulated his view on the necessity of justice for law with the statement, '*nam mihi lex esse non videtur, quae justa non fuerit*', which translates to 'for I think a law that is not just, is not actually a law.'
In what context did Augustine of Hippo discuss the idea that an unjust law is not a law?
Answer: While examining the problem of evil
Explanation: Augustine of Hippo addressed the concept that an unjust law is not a law within his broader theological discourse on the problem of evil. He linked the existence of unjust laws to human deviations from divine goodness and justice.
Which major work by Thomas Aquinas extensively discusses the legitimacy of man-made laws?
Answer: *Summa Theologica*
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas's seminal work, the *Summa Theologica*, provides a comprehensive examination of jurisprudence, including detailed discussions on the nature, purpose, and legitimacy of man-made laws.
According to Thomas Aquinas, what is the first criterion for a man-made law to be considered legitimate?
Answer: It must be enacted for the common good.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas identified the purpose of a law as its primary criterion for legitimacy. A just law must be enacted for the common good of the community, aiming to promote collective well-being.
Which condition did Thomas Aquinas set for a law to be obeyed concerning its creator?
Answer: The creator must be acting within the proper scope of their power.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas stipulated that for a law to be obeyed, it must be enacted by an authority acting within the proper scope of their power, ensuring that the law originates from a legitimate governance and does not exceed its rightful jurisdiction.
What did Thomas Aquinas specify regarding the form of a legitimate law?
Answer: Its burden should be equal and apply fairly to all.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas specified that a legitimate law must be equitable in its form and application, meaning its burden should be distributed equally and it must apply fairly to all members of the community.
What consideration did Thomas Aquinas add regarding the act of disobeying a law?
Answer: Disobedience should not cause harm or lead to evil acts.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas noted that disobedience to a law should not itself cause harm or lead individuals into committing evil acts, referencing the principle that avoiding oppression is always lawful.
What did Thomas Aquinas mean by the "common good" in the context of legitimate laws?
Answer: The overall welfare and flourishing of the community.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas defined the "common good" as the collective welfare and flourishing of the entire community or society. Legitimate laws, in his view, are those enacted with the primary aim of promoting this shared well-being.
How did Aquinas reconcile the authority of law with its potential injustice?
Answer: By setting criteria for legitimacy (purpose, author, form) and cautioning against harmful disobedience.
Explanation: Thomas Aquinas reconciled the authority of law with its potential injustice by establishing criteria for legal legitimacy—namely, purpose (common good), author (proper authority), and form (equity). He also advised that disobedience should be carefully considered to avoid causing greater disorder or harm.
How did Augustine's view on unjust laws connect with his broader theological concerns?
Answer: He linked them to human departures from God's goodness and the problem of evil.
Explanation: Augustine's view on unjust laws was intrinsically connected to his theological concerns about evil, as he saw injustice in laws as a manifestation of human departures from divine goodness.
What does the text suggest about the relationship between Aquinas's criteria for legitimate laws and secular laws?
Answer: They are generally understood to apply to secular laws as well.
Explanation: While rooted in theological and philosophical reasoning, Aquinas's criteria for legitimate laws—purpose for common good, proper authority, and equitable form—are generally understood to apply to secular, man-made laws as well, providing a framework for evaluating their justice and binding force.
Henry David Thoreau, in *Civil Disobedience*, questioned whether individuals should always obey unjust laws without question.
Answer: True
Explanation: Henry David Thoreau, in his essay *Civil Disobedience*, critically examined the moral obligation to obey laws, particularly questioning the automatic compliance with unjust statutes.
Martin Luther King Jr. referenced Socrates and Plato in his *Letter from Birmingham Jail* when discussing unjust laws.
Answer: False
Explanation: This statement is false. In his *Letter from Birmingham Jail*, Martin Luther King Jr. referenced Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, drawing upon their philosophical traditions regarding the nature of just and unjust laws, rather than Socrates and Plato.
Martin Luther King Jr. argued that Jim Crow laws were inherently unjust and should be obeyed.
Answer: False
Explanation: Martin Luther King Jr. argued precisely the opposite: that Jim Crow laws were inherently unjust and therefore lacked moral and legal legitimacy, justifying resistance and civil disobedience against them.
Henry David Thoreau suggested that the only response to an unjust law is to obey it.
Answer: False
Explanation: Henry David Thoreau suggested that obedience is not the only response to an unjust law. He questioned whether individuals should passively obey, attempt reform while obeying, or transgress the law, implying a need for active moral consideration.
Henry David Thoreau suggested that the only response to an unjust law is to obey it.
Answer: False
Explanation: Henry David Thoreau suggested that obedience is not the only response to an unjust law. He questioned whether individuals should passively obey, attempt reform while obeying, or transgress the law, implying a need for active moral consideration.
Civil disobedience, as advocated by Thoreau and King Jr., involves secretly breaking unjust laws.
Answer: False
Explanation: Civil disobedience, as advocated by Thoreau and King Jr., typically involves the open and public violation of unjust laws as a form of protest, rather than secret actions. It often entails accepting the legal consequences.
The Radbruch formula, mentioned in the text, was first formulated in the 20th century.
Answer: True
Explanation: The Radbruch formula, a significant contribution to legal philosophy concerning unjust laws, was indeed first formulated in the 20th century, specifically in the post-World War II era.
Thoreau's questioning implied that passive obedience to unjust laws might not be the morally correct response.
Answer: True
Explanation: Thoreau's questioning implied that passive obedience to unjust laws is not necessarily the morally correct response, urging individuals to consider active engagement and potential transgression.
The Radbruch formula is related to the concept of unjust laws losing their legal character.
Answer: True
Explanation: The Radbruch formula directly addresses the concept that extremely unjust laws may forfeit their legal character, proposing a threshold beyond which legality ceases to apply.
In *Civil Disobedience*, Henry David Thoreau posed a central question about how individuals should respond to unjust laws. What were the options he considered?
Answer: Obey them, attempt to amend them while obeying, or transgress them immediately.
Explanation: Henry David Thoreau, in *Civil Disobedience*, explored the moral dilemma posed by unjust laws, presenting three potential responses: passive obedience, attempting reform while still obeying, or direct transgression of the law.
Whom did Martin Luther King Jr. reference in his *Letter from Birmingham Jail* regarding the nature of unjust laws?
Answer: Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas
Explanation: Martin Luther King Jr., in his seminal *Letter from Birmingham Jail*, drew upon the philosophical traditions of Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas when articulating his arguments against unjust laws and advocating for civil disobedience.
How did Martin Luther King Jr. apply natural law principles to Jim Crow laws?
Answer: He argued Jim Crow laws were inherently unjust and should be resisted.
Explanation: Martin Luther King Jr. applied natural law principles by asserting that Jim Crow laws, being fundamentally unjust and contrary to higher moral law, lacked true legal validity and therefore warranted resistance, including civil disobedience.
What is the underlying principle of civil disobedience advocated by Thoreau and King Jr.?
Answer: Intentional, often open, violation of unjust laws as protest.
Explanation: The underlying principle of civil disobedience, as articulated by Thoreau and King Jr., involves the deliberate and often public violation of laws deemed unjust, undertaken as a form of moral protest aimed at achieving social or legal reform.
The Radbruch formula, mentioned in the text, relates to:
Answer: The relationship between law, justice, and morality concerning unjust laws.
Explanation: The Radbruch formula, formulated in the post-WWII era, addresses the critical intersection of law, justice, and morality, proposing that extremely unjust laws may forfeit their legal character, thereby offering a philosophical framework for confronting oppressive legal systems.
What was the implied call to action in Thoreau's questioning of how to deal with unjust laws?
Answer: To consider active engagement beyond mere obedience.
Explanation: Thoreau's questioning implied a call for active moral engagement with unjust laws, suggesting that passive compliance is insufficient and that individuals should consider more direct actions, such as amendment or transgression, to uphold justice.
In Indian philosophy, *Ṛta* defines rules for law and truth based on natural order.
Answer: True
Explanation: In Indian philosophy, *Ṛta* (Rta) represents the fundamental principle of cosmic order, truth, and righteousness that underpins all existence, including natural laws, moral precepts, and societal structures.
According to Indian philosophy, *Ṛta* is a principle that even gods must obey.
Answer: True
Explanation: Indian philosophy posits *Ṛta* as a fundamental cosmic order and truth that is supreme, binding even divine beings. This underscores its role as an ultimate standard that transcends individual will or authority.
In Indian philosophy, divine beings are considered the creators of *Ṛta*.
Answer: False
Explanation: Contrary to this assertion, Indian philosophy posits that divine beings are not the creators of *Ṛta*. Instead, they act as ministers or agents who manifest and uphold this cosmic order.
The Indian concept of *Ṛta* is comparable to a universal justice or cosmic order.
Answer: True
Explanation: The Indian concept of *Ṛta* represents a principle of cosmic order, truth, and righteousness that governs the universe. It serves as the fundamental basis for natural and moral laws, and is considered an ultimate standard that even deities are bound by.
The concept of *Ṛta* in Indian philosophy suggests that natural order is subordinate to divine will.
Answer: False
Explanation: The concept of *Ṛta* in Indian philosophy posits that natural order is supreme and even divine will is subordinate to it, or at least must conform to it. *Ṛta* represents the ultimate cosmic truth and order.
What is the term in Indian philosophy for the concept defining rules for law and truth based on natural order?
Answer: *Rta*
Explanation: In Indian philosophy, the concept of *Ṛta* (Rta) denotes the principle that governs cosmic order, truth, and righteousness, serving as the foundation for both natural laws and moral precepts.
How is the authority of *Ṛta* described in Indian philosophy?
Answer: It is a form of natural order so high that even the gods must obey it.
Explanation: Indian philosophy posits *Ṛta* as a fundamental cosmic order and truth that is supreme, binding even divine beings. This underscores its role as an ultimate standard that transcends individual will or authority.
According to Indian philosophy, what is the role of divine beings in relation to *Ṛta*?
Answer: They are agents and ministers who manifest *Ṛta*.
Explanation: In Indian philosophy, divine beings are not the creators or governors of *Ṛta*. Instead, they act as its agents and ministers, embodying and enacting its principles through their actions and judgments.
The Indian concept of *Ṛta* can be understood as similar to:
Answer: A principle of cosmic order and truth
Explanation: The Indian concept of *Ṛta* is analogous to a principle of cosmic order, truth, and righteousness that governs the universe. It serves as the fundamental basis for natural and moral laws, and is considered an ultimate standard that even deities are bound by.